mirror of
https://github.com/Brandon-Rozek/website.git
synced 2024-11-13 20:27:29 -05:00
185 lines
No EOL
6 KiB
Markdown
185 lines
No EOL
6 KiB
Markdown
---
|
||
date: 2023-01-27 22:01:54-05:00
|
||
draft: false
|
||
math: true
|
||
medium_enabled: true
|
||
medium_post_id: 5fb876d4d819
|
||
tags:
|
||
- Formal Methods
|
||
title: Readable Lean 3 Proofs
|
||
---
|
||
|
||
*Important Note: This blog post uses the Lean 3 syntax*
|
||
|
||
Interactive theorem provers are notorious for showcasing unreadable proofs. Let's illustrate our point with a couple examples and discuss various ways we can make it more readable.
|
||
|
||
## Disjunction Elimination
|
||
|
||
Disjunction Elimination or proof by cases is a rule of inference that states the following. Consider you have the following three proofs:
|
||
|
||
1. $p \vee q$
|
||
2. $p \rightarrow r$
|
||
3. $q \rightarrow r$
|
||
|
||
Then it doesn't matter if it is $p$ rather than $q$ that holds, in the end $r$ holds. Wikipedia has a [nice example](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Disjunction_elimination) of this concept. I numbered the statements to correspond to the above.
|
||
|
||
> 1. It is true that either I'm inside or I'm outside.
|
||
> 2. If I'm inside, I have my wallet on me.
|
||
> 3. If I'm outside, I have my wallet on me.
|
||
>
|
||
> Therefore, I have my wallet on me.
|
||
|
||
Now let's go over a corresponding proof in Lean.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example (p q r : Prop) : ((p → r) ∧ (q → r) ∧ (p ∨ q)) → r := begin
|
||
intro H,
|
||
cases H,
|
||
cases H_right,
|
||
cases H_right_right,
|
||
case or.inl
|
||
{
|
||
exact H_left H_right_right,
|
||
},
|
||
case or.inr
|
||
{
|
||
exact H_right_left H_right_right,
|
||
},
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
We can see a rough example of proof by cases at work. However, it's extremely hard to follow unless we try to emulate the proof state ourselves. What if I say that it doesn't have to be this way? That in fact, we can have proofs that are more readable. First let's start by replacing `intro` with `assume` and add labels to each of our cases.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example (p q r : Prop) : ((p → r) ∧ (q → r) ∧ (p ∨ q)) → r := begin
|
||
assume H : ((p → r) ∧ (q → r) ∧ (p ∨ q)),
|
||
cases H with H_pr H_rest,
|
||
cases H_rest with H_qr H_pq,
|
||
cases H_pq,
|
||
case or.inl : H_p
|
||
{
|
||
exact H_pr H_p,
|
||
},
|
||
case or.inr : H_q
|
||
{
|
||
exact H_qr H_q,
|
||
},
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Now we know what `H` is just by looking at the proof. Sadly the cases don't exactly tell us what is contained in each of the hypotheses. But at least they're labeled to give us a clue. We can do better by replacing the initial `cases` statements with `have` and `exact` with `show`.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example (p q r : Prop) : ((p → r) ∧ (q → r) ∧ (p ∨ q)) → r := begin
|
||
assume H : ((p → r) ∧ (q → r) ∧ (p ∨ q)),
|
||
have H_pr : p → r := and.left H,
|
||
have H_qr : q → r := and.left (and.right H),
|
||
have H_pq : p ∨ q := and.right (and.right H),
|
||
cases H_pq,
|
||
case or.inl : H_p
|
||
{
|
||
show r, from H_pr H_p,
|
||
},
|
||
case or.inr : H_q
|
||
{
|
||
show r, from H_qr H_q,
|
||
},
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Now we have almost a complete picture of what all of our hypotheses are. The only two that are left unspecified are `H_p` and `H_q`. Though we can easily infer what they are by the label. Also by replacing `exact` with `show`, we have insight on what is trying to be proved at that given point.
|
||
|
||
The whole beginning of the proof is setting up the problem. Luckily, Lean provides a more concise syntax that better matches how the problem would be presented.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example {p q r : Prop} (H_pr : p → r) (H_qr : q → r) (H_pq : p ∨ q) : r := begin
|
||
cases H_pq,
|
||
case or.inl : H_p
|
||
{
|
||
show r, from H_pr H_p,
|
||
},
|
||
case or.inr : H_q
|
||
{
|
||
show r, from H_qr H_q,
|
||
},
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Finally, if we wanted to condense this more, we can make use of the built in `or.elim` theorem.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example {p q r : Prop} (H_pr : p → r) (H_qr : q → r) (H_pq : p ∨ q) : r := begin
|
||
show r, from or.elim H_pq H_pr H_qr,
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
## Negation Introduction
|
||
|
||
Now let's showcase a more complicated example. Negation introduction or proof by contradiction. Consider that we have the following two proofs:
|
||
|
||
1. $p \rightarrow q$
|
||
2. $p \rightarrow \neg q$
|
||
|
||
Then by negation introduction, we have a proof of $\neg p$.
|
||
|
||
The proof is going to rely on the law of excluded middle. That is $p \vee \neg p$ holds.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
axiom LEM {p : Prop}: p ∨ ¬ p
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
The proof also relies on the following property about negation
|
||
$$
|
||
\neg p \iff (p \rightarrow false)
|
||
$$
|
||
Now let's try to prove negation introduction using the `cases` tactic.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p → q) (H_nq : p → ¬q) : ¬p := begin
|
||
have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM,
|
||
cases H_LEM,
|
||
case or.inl : H_p
|
||
{
|
||
have H_nq : ¬q := H_nq H_p,
|
||
have H_qf : q → false := H_nq,
|
||
have H_q : q := H_pq H_p,
|
||
have H_f : false := H_qf H_q,
|
||
-- Can prove anything with a falsity
|
||
-- (Reductio ad absurdum)
|
||
show ¬p, from false.rec (¬p) H_f,
|
||
},
|
||
case or.inr : H_np
|
||
{
|
||
show ¬p, from H_np,
|
||
},
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Sadly this proof is too complicated to condense in one line with `or.elim`. However, we can set it up by creating subproofs with `have`.
|
||
|
||
```lean
|
||
example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p → q) (H_nq : p → ¬q) : ¬p := begin
|
||
have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM,
|
||
have H_npp : ¬p → ¬p := by {
|
||
assume H_np : ¬p,
|
||
show ¬p, from H_np,
|
||
},
|
||
have H_pp : p → ¬p := by {
|
||
assume H_p : p,
|
||
have H_nq : ¬q := H_nq H_p,
|
||
have H_qf : q → false := H_nq,
|
||
have H_q : q := H_pq H_p,
|
||
have H_f : false := H_qf H_q,
|
||
show ¬p, from false.rec (¬p) H_f,
|
||
},
|
||
show ¬p, from or.elim H_LEM H_pp H_npp,
|
||
end
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
## Conclusion
|
||
|
||
When most people are taught how to write proofs in an interactive theorem prover, they are shown tactics such as `cases`, `split`, `left`, `right`, etc. These tactics manipulate the proof state which is shown to the developer when creating the proof. However, as a line in a proof it provides minimal insight.
|
||
|
||
We can take the guesswork out of figuring out the proof state by carefully selecting tactics which allow us to explicitely show the object being constructed. In Lean, these are `assume`, `have`, and `show`. Also making use of the inference rules themselves such as `or.elim` is a great alternative to `cases`, and `and.intro` is a great alternative to split.
|
||
|
||
If you have any other techniques on making ITP proofs more readable, please let me know. |