From 09b75a543b32b86fd3b0e2d91d13c9aba93a41b4 Mon Sep 17 00:00:00 2001 From: Brandon Rozek Date: Sun, 17 Mar 2024 23:11:17 -0400 Subject: [PATCH] Updated lean post --- content/blog/lean3-tutorial.md | 21 +- content/blog/lean4-tutorial.md | 495 +++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++ content/blog/leantactics.md | 7 +- 3 files changed, 512 insertions(+), 11 deletions(-) create mode 100644 content/blog/lean4-tutorial.md diff --git a/content/blog/lean3-tutorial.md b/content/blog/lean3-tutorial.md index cd62ba6..8b7f783 100644 --- a/content/blog/lean3-tutorial.md +++ b/content/blog/lean3-tutorial.md @@ -7,6 +7,9 @@ math: true medium_enabled: false --- +Warning: This post covers Lean 3 which has been deprecated +in favor of Lean 4. Check out my [updated tutorial](/blog/lean4-tutorial/). + Lean is an interactive theorem prover created by Microsoft. As part of the RPI logic group, I gave a tutorial introducing Lean and showcasing how to prove some statements within it. This post aims to cover the concepts I went over at the time and can be used as an initial reference. @@ -66,7 +69,7 @@ Given a conjunctive hypothesis, the `cases` tactic will create two new hypothesi ### Disjunctive Introduction -Given any statement $P$, we can introduce an arbitrary formula as a disjunct. More intuitively, if Jarold is above the age of 10, then he is above the age of 10 or he likes lolipops. It does not change the truth value of the statement. +Given any statement $P$, we can introduce an arbitrary formula as a disjunct. More intuitively, if Jarold is above the age of 10, then he is above the age of 10 or he likes lollipops. It does not change the truth value of the statement. The inference based way of representing this is as follows: @@ -98,7 +101,7 @@ The form of disjunctive elimination included in Lean is more commonly known as * > > Therefore, I have my wallet on me. -To acheive this in Lean using the inference based approach. +To achieve this in Lean using the inference based approach. ```lean example {p q r : Prop} (H_pr : p → r) (H_qr : q → r) (H_pq : p ∨ q) : r := begin @@ -320,7 +323,7 @@ end Lets say we have the following forall statement: $\forall a \in \alpha: p a \implies b$. -Now lets say we have the follwing existential: $\exists x, p x$. +Now lets say we have the following existential: $\exists x, p x$. Using these, we can derive $b$. @@ -345,7 +348,7 @@ end One of the biggest use cases of an interactive theorem prover is in program verification. -To help represent recursive data strcutres, we +To help represent recursive data structures, we have the notion of an *inductive type*. Let's create a custom representation of a list. @@ -360,7 +363,7 @@ inductive CustomList (T : Type) Some examples of a list here include `cnil`, `ccons(0, cnil)`, and `ccons(1, ccons(0, cnil))`. -For convinience, we'll open the `CustomList` namespace +For convenience, we'll open the `CustomList` namespace so that we don't have to refer each constructor (`cnil`/`ccons`) by it. @@ -368,7 +371,7 @@ so that we don't have to refer each constructor open CustomList ``` -### Functions over Inductive Typess +### Functions over Inductive Types To define a function over an inductive type, we need to cover each of the constructors. @@ -447,7 +450,7 @@ The `rewrite` command allows us to replace instances of functions with their def The `calc` environment allows us to perform multiple rewrites in order to get closer to that end. -Instead of explicitely making use of `rec_on`, we can use the `induction` tactic. +Instead of explicitly making use of `rec_on`, we can use the `induction` tactic. ```lean theorem append_nil2 {α : Type} (as : CustomList α) : cappend as cnil = as := begin @@ -467,7 +470,7 @@ theorem append_nil2 {α : Type} (as : CustomList α) : cappend as cnil = as := b end ``` -Lean also supports writing the theorems in a similar inducive syntax as the definitions. Though to me it looks slightly confusing. +Lean also supports writing the theorems in a similar inductive syntax as the definitions. Though to me it looks slightly confusing. ```lean theorem append_nil3 {α : Type} : ∀ as : CustomList α, cappend as cnil = as @@ -550,6 +553,6 @@ Notice that a couple times in the proof, make use of a tactic called `linarith`. ## Conclusion -That concludes the examples I gave for my talk. For each proof, you can see that I included at least two different ways of going about proving it. I generally prefer the inference style method where we explicitely call on `Or.elim` and the like. Though when it comes to double induction, I have not figured out how to apply `rec_on` multiple times in a clean way. +That concludes the examples I gave for my talk. For each proof, you can see that I included at least two different ways of going about proving it. I generally prefer the inference style method where we explicitly call on `Or.elim` and the like. Though when it comes to double induction, I have not figured out how to apply `rec_on` multiple times in a clean way. In the process of making this tutorial, I released other lean posts. One that I recommend checking out is ["Readable Lean 3 Proofs"](/blog/readable-lean3-proofs/). In it, I give my opinions on how to make the written out proofs more human friendly. diff --git a/content/blog/lean4-tutorial.md b/content/blog/lean4-tutorial.md new file mode 100644 index 0000000..741ba85 --- /dev/null +++ b/content/blog/lean4-tutorial.md @@ -0,0 +1,495 @@ +--- +title: "Lean 4 Tutorial" +date: 2024-03-17T22:27:32-04:00 +draft: false +tags: ["Formal Methods"] +math: true +medium_enabled: false +--- + +Lean is an interactive theorem prover created by Microsoft. +In 2021, they performed a major transition from Lean 3 to Lean 4. +This transition changed the syntax and tactics used within proofs +and caused major library developers such as Mathlib to transition. + +Last year I wrote a [Lean 3 tutorial](/blog/lean3-tutorial) which showcases +how to go about constructing proofs for several small problems. +After revisiting Lean 4 recently, +I decided that Mathlib support is comprehensive and stable enough to make +the switch. + +This post is the same as the Lean 3 tutorial that I wrote last year, except +that the examples have been updated to the latest syntax. + + +## Propositional Logic (Intuitionist Fragment) + +To prove something in Lean, we need to construct an object of that type. + +### Conjunctive Introduction +To start off let us prove the statement $P \wedge Q$ given both $P$ and $Q$ individually. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_p : p) (H_q : q) : (p ∧ q) := by + exact show p ∧ q from And.intro H_p H_q +``` + +This shows an application of conjunctive introduction. We created the object $P \wedge Q$ by applying the theorem `And.intro` to both hypotheses `H_p` which contains $P$ and `H_q` which contains $Q$. + + +Another way of going about this proof is by *transforming the goal to another equivalent one*. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_p : p) (H_q : q) : (p ∧ q) := by + constructor + case left => + exact show p from H_p + case right => + exact show q from H_q +``` + +In this proof, we make use of the `constructor` tactic. Given a conjunctive goal $P \wedge Q$, this tactic replaces it with two subgoals $P$ and $Q$. We can then apply the hypotheses to solve the problem. + +### Conjunctive Elimination + +Given the proof of $P \wedge Q$, we can derive $P$ from it. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p ∧ q) : p := by + exact show p from And.left H_pq +``` + +In the example above, we apply the inference `And.left` to be able to derive the left side of a conjunct. Similarly to the last inference rule, there is a tactic based way to go about it. Tactic based methods are generally more prevalent within the ITP community. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p ∧ q) : p := by + cases' H_pq with H_p H_q -- p, q + exact show p from H_p +``` + +Given a conjunctive hypothesis, the `cases'` tactic will create two new hypothesis from it. The two labels after the `with` is to specify the names of these hypotheses. The string `--` denotes the start of a comment; I left a small comment to remind me the ordering of the conjuncts. + +### Disjunctive Introduction + +Given any statement $P$, we can introduce an arbitrary formula as a disjunct. More intuitively, if Jarold is above the age of 10, then he is above the age of 10 or he likes lollipops. It does not change the truth value of the statement. + +The inference based way of representing this is as follows: + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_p : p) : (p ∨ q) := by + exact show p ∨ q from Or.intro_left q H_p +``` + +In the more popular tactic based notion. We use the tactic `left` or `right` to denote which side we're going to attempt to prove. If we're trying to prove $P \vee Q$ and we have $P$ then we will prove the left side. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_p : p) : (p ∨ q) := by + left + exact show p from H_p +``` + +### Disjunctive Elimination + +The form of disjunctive elimination included in Lean is more commonly known as *proof by cases*. That is if you know either $A$ or $B$ is true. That is, $A \vee B$. And, you can derive $C$ from $A$ as well as $C$ from $B$. Then it doesn't matter which of $A$ or $B$ is true, because you can derive $C$ regardless. + +[Wikipedia](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Disjunction_elimination) has a nice intuitive example: +> If I'm inside, I have my wallet on me. +> +> If I'm outside, I have my wallet on me. +> +> It is true that either I'm inside or I'm outside. +> +> Therefore, I have my wallet on me. + +To achieve this in Lean using the inference based approach. + +```lean +example {p q r : Prop} (H_pr : p → r) (H_qr : q → r) (H_pq : p ∨ q) : r := by + exact show r from Or.elim H_pq H_pr H_qr +``` + +Alternatively, via the tactic based approach + +```lean +example {p q r : Prop} (H_pr : p → r) (H_qr : q → r) (H_pq : p ∨ q) : r := by + cases' H_pq with H_p H_q + case inl => + -- Assume p, apply modus ponens with H_pr + exact show r from H_pr H_p + case inr => + -- Assume q, apply modus ponens with H_qr + exact show r from H_qr H_q +``` + +## Negation + +Traditional interactive theorem provers such as Coq focused on the constructivist approach to theorem proving. +This allows them to export proofs as programs in OCaml. +Lean places less of an emphasis on this approach and instead supports the proof by contradiction style +you see in classical theorem proving. + +During the tutorial, I decided to make this distinction explicit by making use of the law of excluded middle. By default, Lean uses the axiom of choice which can then be used to derive the law of excluded middle, but I cut that part out for brevity. + +In other words, if you want to perform a proof by contradiction, don't use the techniques shown in this section and instead use the `by_contra` tactic. + +Declare the axiom of law of excluded middle: + +```lean +axiom LEM {p : Prop}: p ∨ ¬ p +``` + +### Negation Introduction + +For negation introduction, let's say we have some proposition $P$. If we can use $P$ to derive a falsity, let's say $Q \wedge \neg Q$ then $P$ must be false. That is, we introduce a negation to make it $\neg P$. + +The structure of the proof will a proof by cases on the law of exclude middle. + +```lean +lemma negation_intro {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p → q) (H_pnq : p → ¬q) : ¬p := by + have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM + + -- Assuming ¬p derive ¬p + have H_npp : ¬p → ¬p := by + intro (H_np : ¬p) + exact show ¬p from H_np + + -- Assuming p derive ¬p + have H_pp : p → ¬p := by + -- Use hypotheses to obtain q and ¬q + intro (H_p : p) + have H_q : q := H_pq H_p + have H_nq : ¬q := H_pnq H_p + + -- We can derive falsity from a direct contradiction + have H_false : False := H_nq H_q + + -- You can derive anything from false + have H_UNUSED: p ∧ ¬p := False.elim H_false + + -- Including what we want, ¬p + exact show ¬p from False.elim H_false + + -- By proof by cases, we derive ¬p + exact show ¬p from Or.elim H_LEM H_pp H_npp +``` + +Lean can tell us which axioms our proof depends on as well. + +```lean +#print axioms negation_intro +``` + +This returns `'negation_intro' depends on axioms: [LEM]`. + +Alternatively, the tactic based approach + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p → q) (H_pnq : p → ¬q) : ¬p := by + have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM + cases' H_LEM with H_p H_np + + case inl => + have H_q : q := H_pq H_p + have H_nq : ¬q := H_pnq H_p + have H_false : False := H_nq H_q + exact show ¬p from False.elim H_false + + case inr => + exact show ¬p from H_np +``` + +As I mentioned before, we do not have to explicitly declare the +axiom of excluded middle. Instead we can make use of Lean's builtin +classical reasoning. + +```lean +example {p q : Prop} (H_pq : p → q) (H_pnq : p → ¬q) : ¬p := by + by_contra H_p + have H_q : q := H_pq H_p + have H_nq : ¬q := H_pnq H_p + exact show False from H_nq H_q +``` + +### Negation Elimination + +One common representation of negation elimination is to remove any double negations. +That is $\neg \neg P$ becomes $P$. + +We'll similarly show this by performing a proof by cases on the law of excluded middle. + +```lean +example {p: Prop} (H_nnp : ¬¬p) : p := by + have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM + + -- Assuming ¬p derive p + have H_np2p : ¬p → p := by + intro (H_np : ¬p) + -- ¬p and ¬¬p are a direct contradiction + have H_false : False := H_nnp H_np + -- Derive our goal from a falsity + exact show p from False.elim H_false + + -- Assuming p derive p + have H_p2p : p → p := by + intro (H_p : p) + exact show p from H_p + + -- By proof by cases, we derive p + exact show p from Or.elim H_LEM H_p2p H_np2p +``` + +Alternatively for the tactic based approach. + +```lean +example {p: Prop} (H_nnp : ¬¬p) : p := by + have H_LEM : p ∨ ¬p := LEM + cases' H_LEM with H_p H_np + + -- Assuming p, derive p + case inl => + exact show p from H_p + + -- Assuming ¬p derive p + case inr => + -- ¬p and ¬¬p are a direct contradiction + have H_false : False := H_nnp H_np + exact show p from False.elim H_false +``` + +## First Order + +Lean is also capable of reasoning over first order logic. In this section, we'll start seeing objects/terms and predicates instead of just propositions. + +For example `{α : Type} {P : α → Prop} ` means that $P$ is a predicate of arity one and takes an object of type $\alpha$. + + +### Forall Elim + +If we have a forall statement, then we can replace the bound variable with an object of that type and remove the forall. Lets say for our example we have the following forall statement: $\forall x \in \mathbb{N}: x \ge 0$. Then we can replace the $x$ with $2$ and get the following formula: $2 \ge 0$. + +```lean +example {α : Type} {P : α → Prop} {y : α} (H : ∀ x : α, P x) : P y := by + exact show P y from H y +``` + +### Forall Intro + +To show that some property holds for all $x$ of a type α, you need to show that it holds +for an arbitrary $x$ of that type. We can introduce this object, by the `intro` command. + +```lean +example {α : Type} {P Q R : α → Prop} (H_pq : ∀ x : α, P x → Q x) (H_qr : ∀ x : α, Q x → R x) : ∀ x : α, P x → R x := by + intro (y: α) + have H_pqx : P y → Q y := H_pq y + have H_qrx : Q y → R y := H_qr y + intro (H_py : P y) + have H_qy : Q y := H_pqx H_py + exact show R y from H_qrx H_qy +``` + +### Exists Intro + +To introduce an existential, you need to show that the formula holds for any object of a certain type. + +```lean +example {α : Type} {P : α → Prop} {y : α} (H: P y) : ∃ x: α, P x := by + exact show ∃ x, P x from Exists.intro y H +``` + +In the tactic based approach, this is done via `exists`: + +```lean +example {α : Type} {P : α → Prop} {y : α} (H: P y) : ∃ x: α, P x := by + exact show ∃ x, P x from by exists y +``` + +### Exists Elim + +Lets say we have the following forall statement: $\forall a \in \alpha: p a \implies b$. + +Now lets say we have the following existential: $\exists x, p x$. + +Using these, we can derive $b$. + +```lean +example {α : Type} {p : α → Prop} {b : Prop} (H_epx : ∃ x, p x) (H_pab : ∀ (a : α), p a → b) : b := by + exact show b from Exists.elim H_epx H_pab +``` + +Alternatively for the tactic based approach: + +```lean +example {α : Type} {p : α → Prop} {b : Prop} (H_epx : ∃ x, p x) (H_pab : ∀ (a : α), p a → b) : b := by + cases' H_epx with c H_pc + have H_pcb : p c → b := H_pab c + exact show b from H_pcb H_pc +``` + +## Inductive Types + +One of the biggest use cases of an interactive +theorem prover is in program verification. +To help represent recursive data structures, we +have the notion of an *inductive type*. + +Let's create a custom representation of a list. +A list can either by empty (`cnil`) or be an element `hd` combined with the rest of some list `tl`. + +```lean +inductive CustomList (T : Type) where +| cnil : CustomList T +| ccons (hd : T) -> (tl : CustomList T) : CustomList T +``` + +Some examples of a list here include `cnil`, +`ccons(0, cnil)`, and `ccons(1, ccons(0, cnil))`. + +For convenience, we'll open the `CustomList` namespace +so that we don't have to refer each constructor +(`cnil`/`ccons`) by it. + +```lean +open CustomList +``` + +### Functions over Inductive Types + +To define a function over an inductive type, +we need to cover each of the constructors. + +For example, let's consider the notion of a list's length. +- If the list is `cnil` then the length is $0$. +- If the list starts with `ccons` then we add 1 to the length of the tail `tl`. + +```lean +def clength {α : Type}: CustomList α → Nat + | cnil => 0 + | (ccons _ as) => 1 + clength as +``` + +We can see the output of a function via the `#eval` command. + +```lean +#eval clength (@cnil Nat) +#eval clength (ccons 2 (ccons 1 cnil)) +``` + +For another example, let us look at appending two lists. As an example if we have the list `[1, 2, 3]` and the list `[4, 5, 6]`, then appending those two lists will create `[1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6]`. + +```lean +def cappend {α : Type} (as bs : CustomList α) : CustomList α := + match as with + | cnil => bs + | ccons a as => ccons a (cappend as bs) +``` + +Example evaluations, make sure these come out to what you expect. + +```lean +#eval cappend (ccons 1 cnil) (ccons 2 cnil) +#eval clength (cappend (ccons 1 cnil) (ccons 2 cnil)) +``` + + +### Theorems over Inductive Types + +Now that we have a data structure and some methods over it. We can now prove some interesting properties. + +First let's start off with the following theorem. + +> Appending `cnil` to a list `as` is equivalent to the list `as`. + +When instantiating an inductive type, the inductive hypothesis is created for it via `recOn`. +Therefore, we can rely on that for the proof. + + +```lean +theorem append_nil {α : Type} (as : CustomList α) : cappend as cnil = as := by + -- Base Case + have H_BASE : (cappend cnil cnil = (@cnil α)) := by rfl + + -- Inductive Step + have H_Inducive : ∀ (hd : α) (tl : CustomList α), cappend tl cnil = tl → cappend (ccons hd tl) cnil = ccons hd tl := by + intro (hd : α) + intro (tl : CustomList α) + intro (IH : cappend tl cnil = tl) + calc + cappend (ccons hd tl) cnil = ccons hd (cappend tl cnil) := by rw [cappend] + _ = ccons hd tl := by rw [IH] + + -- Apply induction principle + exact CustomList.recOn (motive := fun x => cappend x cnil = x) + as + H_BASE + H_Inducive +``` + +The `rewrite`/`rw` command allows us to replace instances of functions with their definitions. The goal is to get both sides of the equality to be syntactically the same. +The `calc` environment allows us to perform multiple rewrites in order to get closer to that end. + + +Instead of explicitly making use of `recOn`, we can use the `induction` tactic. + +```lean +theorem append_nil2 {α : Type} (as : CustomList α) : cappend as cnil = as := by + induction as + + case cnil => + calc + cappend cnil cnil = cnil := by rw [cappend] + _ = cnil := by exact rfl + + case ccons hd tl IH => + calc + cappend (ccons hd tl) cnil = ccons hd (cappend tl cnil) := by rw [cappend] + _ = ccons hd tl := by rw [IH] + +``` + +### Double Induction + +For our next example, we'll need to perform induction on two lists. + +> Given two lists `as` and `bs`. The length of their append is the same as the length of each individual list added together. + +```lean +theorem length_append_sum {α : Type} (as bs : CustomList α) : clength (cappend as bs) = clength as + clength bs := by + induction as + induction bs + + case cnil.cnil => + calc + clength (cappend cnil cnil) = clength cnil := by rw [cappend] + _ = 0 := by rw [clength] + _ = 0 + 0 := by linarith + _ = (clength cnil) + (clength cnil) := by rw [clength] + + case cnil.ccons hd tl _ => + calc + clength (cappend cnil (ccons hd tl)) = clength (ccons hd tl) := by rw [cappend] + _ = 0 + clength (ccons hd tl) := by linarith + _ = clength cnil + clength (ccons hd tl) := by rw [clength] + + case ccons hd tl IH => + calc + clength (cappend (ccons hd tl) bs) = clength (ccons hd (cappend tl bs)) := by rw [cappend] + _ = 1 + clength (cappend tl bs) := by rw [clength] + _ = 1 + (clength tl + clength bs) := by rw [IH] + _ = (1 + clength tl) + clength bs := by linarith + _ = clength (ccons hd tl) + clength bs := by rw [clength] + + -- Lean intelligently wlogs the fourth case +``` + +Notice that a couple times in the proof, make use of a tactic called `linarith`. This stands for "linear arithmetic" and helps solve goals involving numbers. I generally employ this rather than figuring out which definitions I need to perform commutativity and associativity rules. + +## Conclusion + +One of my favorite things about Lean is the ability to make proofs +more readable by making use of the `have`, `calc`, and `rewrite` +tactics. I do find it easier, however, to use the `induction` tactic +for inductive proofs. Especially when dealing with nested +inductions as writing out the cases explicitly can be daunting. + +If you catch any mistakes in me converting this post, let me know. +Otherwise feel free to email me if you have any questions. diff --git a/content/blog/leantactics.md b/content/blog/leantactics.md index 046e7c4..2fd4df0 100644 --- a/content/blog/leantactics.md +++ b/content/blog/leantactics.md @@ -6,10 +6,13 @@ medium_enabled: true medium_post_id: adea1a69ddc8 tags: - Formal Methods -title: Lean Theorem Prover Tactics +title: Lean 3 Theorem Prover Tactics --- -I've recently been playing with the Lean Theorem Prover. I am impressed with how some of the mathematics community decided to extend this project via [mathlib](https://leanprover-community.github.io/) and really make proving theorems in this framework easy and enjoyable. +Warning: This post covers Lean 3 which has been deprecated +in favor of Lean 4. + +I've recently been playing with the Lean 3 Theorem Prover. I am impressed with how some of the mathematics community decided to extend this project via [mathlib](https://leanprover-community.github.io/) and really make proving theorems in this framework easy and enjoyable. Normally one of the most frustrating parts of theorem proving is having to justify what may seem to be a simple goal. Luckily, mathlib helps us out by [introducing tactics](https://leanprover-community.github.io/mathlib_docs/tactics.html) that can take some of these simple goals to the finish line.